David Hume Did Not Create the Is-Ought Problem
4 minutes • 785 words
Table of contents
While reviewing my simplification of David Hume’s Treatise of Human Nature Book 3, I came upon a strange wiki article called Hume’s Is-Ought Problem:
Hume calls for caution against such inferences in the absence of any explanation of how the ought-statements follow from the is-statements. But how exactly can an “ought” be derived from an “is”? The question, prompted by Hume’s small paragraph, has become one of the central questions of ethical theory, and Hume is usually assigned the position that such a derivation is impossible. This complete severing of “is” from “ought” has been given the graphic designation of Hume’s Guillotine.
Did whoever create the Is-Ought problem even bother to take the contextof that paragraph with the rest of Book 3?
Hume merely described the flaw in the way of how shallow-minded moral philosophers make moral rules. First, they explain the nature of things using reason. Suddenly and discretely, they inject their bias and personal feelings into the nature of things (is), as to create casuistic moral rules (ought). This then makes a work of reason become an unreasonable work of subjective bias.
It does not mean that deriving ‘ought’ from ‘is’ is impossible.
In every system of morality, the author proceeds in the ordinary way of reasoning and establishes God, or makes observations on human affairs. Suddenly, instead of the usual propositions of ‘is’ and ‘is not’, I meet propositions of ‘should’ and ‘should not’.
This change is imperceptible, but is of final consequence. This ‘should’ or ‘should not’ expresses some new relation or affirmation [from their bias or personal feelings]. This new relation should be observed and explained at the same time that a reason should be given for what seems inconceivable [what was the cause of his bias]. How can this new relation be a deduction from other deductions entirely different from it [his personal feelings]?
An easy example is the Ten Commandments. In it, the author writes the ‘is’ in Exodus 19:3 that the Israelites did leave Egypt, as a matter of fact.
But then, the author adds his bias and personality into the fact or ‘is’ that was stated, in order to create a personal rule or ‘ought’:
According to Hume’s principle, this tactic is improper because had the Israelites known that their freedom from Egypt would have a price, as the Ten Commandments, then surely, not all of them would have fled Egypt.
So it’s unfair for the ‘is’ to be converted to ‘ought’, as a new relation that is connected to the author instead of the freedom of the Israelites.
To prevent this problem, Hume advises people to be mindful of moralists who inject their biases very subtly as to create moral rules that favor themselves, and are therefore illogical.
This explains:
- why the Israelites still had polytheism even after they moved to the desert
- why Moses (the author behind the idea of God) had to impose severe punishments on his own people
You could think of the Kingdom of God as a political party (with a ready-to-use set of political policies). People who were preaching the Kingdom of God were actually preaching a political party that was competing with others. Anyone who was following the other political party was committing ‘sin’.
Most of the prophets in the Old Testament were political propagandists (who advised policies against foreign invaders) more than being moralists.
Morals are Based on Feelings
Hume explains that morals are not based on the reason of humans, but on their feelings. It is these feelings that humans use to base reasoning on.
An easier example, that doesn’t refer to God, is a celibate man saying that sexual diseases are caused by sex. Therefore, sex should be banned.
He correctly says that sexual diseases are caused by sex, from his observation of human affairs. This is the ‘is’ part. But he jumps into an ‘ought’ by saying that people shouldn’t have sex. In this way, he imposes his own beliefs on others, all of which are rooted in his feelings, without taking into account the feelings or situation of others.