Physics and Mechanism
7 minutes • 1326 words
Most theorists have a constant predilection for explanations borrowed from physics, mechanics, or dynamics.
Some would be satisfied if they could account for all phenomena by the motion of molecules attracting one another according to certain laws.
Others are more exact: they wouldsuppress attractions acting at a distance; their molecules would follow rectilinear paths, from which they would only be deviated by impacts.
Others again, such as Hertz, suppress the forces as well, but suppose their molecules subjected to geometrical connections analogous, for instance, to those of articulated systems; thus, they wish to reduce dynamics to a kind of kinematics. In a word, they all wish to bend nature into a certain form, and unless they can do this they cannot be satisfied.
Is Nature flexible enough for this?
We shall examine this question in Chapter 12, àpropos of Maxwell’s theory.
Every time that the principles of least action and energy are satisfied, we shall see that not only is there always a mechanical explanation possible, but that there is an unlimited number of such explanations.
By means of a well-known theorem due to Königs, it may be shown that we can explain everything in an unlimited number of ways, by connections after the manner of Hertz, or, again, by central forces.
No doubt it may be just as easily demonstrated that everything may be explained by simple impacts. For this, let us bear in mind that it is not enough to be content with the ordinary matter of which we are aware by means of our senses, and the movements of which we observe directly.
Ordinary matter is either composed of:
- atoms, or
- The internal movements of these escape our senses
- one of those subtle fluids, called the ether
- This has always played so important a rôle in physical theories.
Often we regard the ether as the only true matter.
The more moderate consider ordinary matter to be condensed ether. There is nothing startling in this conception.
But others only reduce its importance still further, and see in matter nothing more than the geometrical locus of singularities in the ether.
Lord Kelvin, for instance, holds what we call matter to be only the locus of those points at which the ether is animated by vortex motions.
Riemann believes it to be locus of those points at which ether is constantly destroyed.
Wiechert or Larmor believes that it is the locus of the points at which the ether has undergone a kind of torsion of a very particular kind.
But why do we apply the mechanical properties of ordinary matter, which is but false matter, to the ether?
The ancient fluids, caloric, electricity, etc., were abandoned when it was seen that heat is not indestructible.
But they were also laid aside for another reason, In materialising them, their individ- uality was, so to speak, emphasised—gaps were opened between them;
these gaps had to be filled in when the sentiment of the unity of Nature became stronger, and when the intimate relations which connect all the parts were perceived.
In multiplying the fluids, not only did the ancient physicists create unnecessary entities, but they destroyed real ties.
It is not enough for a theory not to affirm false relations; it must not conceal true relations.
Does our ether actually exist? We know the origin of our belief in the ether. If light takes several years to reach us from a distant star, it is no longer on the star, nor is it on the earth. It must be somewhere, and supported, so to speak, by some material agency.
The same idea may be expressed in a more mathematical and more abstract form. What we note are the changes undergone by the material molecules.
A photographic plate experiences the consequences of a phenomenon of which the incandescent mass of a star was the scene several years before.
In ordinary mechanics, the state of the system under consideration depends only on its state at the moment immediately preceding.
The system therefore satisfies certain differential equations. On the other hand, if we did not believe in the ether, the state of the material universe would depend not only on the state immediately preceding, but also on much older states; the system would satisfy equations of finite differences. The ether was invented to escape this breaking down of the laws of general mechanics.
Still, this would only compel us to fill the interplanetary space with ether, but not to make it penetrate into the midst of the material media.
Fizeau’s experiment goes further. By the interference of rays which have passed through the air or water in/ motion, it seems to show us two different media penetrating each other, and yet being displaced with respect to each other.
The ether is all but in our grasp. Experiments can be conceived in which we come closer still to it. Assume that Newton’s principle of the equality of action and reaction is not true if applied to matter alone, and that this can be proved. The geometrical sum of all the forces applied to all the molecules would no longer be zero.
If we did not wish to change the whole of the science of mechanics, we should have to introduce the ether, in order that the action which matter apparently undergoes should be counterbalanced by the reaction of matter on something. Or again, suppose we discover that optical and electrical phenomena are influenced by the motion of the earth.
It would follow that those phenomena might reveal to us not only the relative motion of material bodies, but also what would seem to be their absolute motion.
It would be necessary to have an ether in order that these so-called absolute movements should not be their displacements with respect to empty space, but with respect to something concrete.
I do not think this ever be accomplished.
If the theory of Lorentz (in Chapter 13) were true then:
- Newton’s principle would not apply to matter alone and
- the difference would not be very far from being within reach of experiment.
On the other hand, many experiments have been made on the influence of the motion of the earth. The results have always been negative.
But if these experiments have been undertaken, it is because we have not been certain beforehand.
According to current theories, the compensation would be only approximate. We might expect to find accurate methods giving positive results.
I think that such a hope is illusory. It was nonetheless interesting to show that a success of this kind would open to us a new world.
I do not believe, in spite of Lorentz, that more exact observations will ever make evident anything else but the relative displacements of material bodies.
Experiments have been made that should have disclosed the terms of the first order; the results were nugatory. Could that have been by chance?
No one has admitted this.
A general explanation was sought, and Lorentz found it.
He showed that the terms of the first order should cancel each other, but not the terms of the second order. Then more exact experiments were made, which were also negative; neither could this be the result of chance.
An explanation was necessary, and was forthcoming; they always are; hypotheses are what we lack the least. But this is not enough.
Who is there who does not think that this leaves to chance far too important a rôle?
Would it not also be a chance that this singular concurrence should cause a certain circumstance to destroy the terms of the first order, and that a totally different but very opportune circumstance should cause those of the second order to vanish?
No; the same explanation must be found for the two cases, and everything tends to show that this explanation would serve equally well for the terms of the higher order, and that the mutual destruction of these terms will be rigorous and absolute.