Who is to be the judge of things?
4 minutes • 712 words
Who is to be the judge of things?
All such questions have the same meaning.
These people demand that a reason shall be given for everything; for they seek a starting-point, and they seek to get this by demonstration, while it is obvious from their actions that they have no conviction.
But their mistake is what we have stated it to be; they seek a reason for things for which no reason can be given; for the starting-point of demonstration is not demonstration.
These, then, might be easily persuaded of this truth, for it is not difficult to grasp.
But those who seek merely compulsion in argument seek what is impossible; for they demand to be allowed to contradict themselves-a claim which contradicts itself from the very first.-But if not all things are relative, but some are self-existent, not everything that appears will be true; for that which appears is apparent to some one; so that he who says all things that appear are true, makes all things relative.
Those who ask for an irresistible argument, and at the same time demand to be called to account for their views, must guard themselves by saying that the truth is not that what appears exists, but that what appears exists for him to whom it appears, and when, and to the sense to which, and under the conditions under which it appears.
If they give an account of their view, but do not give it in this way, they will soon find themselves contradicting themselves.
The same thing may appear to be honey to the sight, but not to the taste, and that, since we have two eyes, things may not appear the same to each, if their sight is unlike.
For to those who for the reasons named some time ago say that what appears is true, and therefore that all things are alike false and true, for things do not appear either the same to all men or always the same to the same man, but often have contrary appearances at the same time (for touch says there are two objects when we cross our fingers, while sight says there is one)-to these we shall say ‘yes, but not to the same sense and in the same part of it and under the same conditions and at the same time’, so that what appears will be with these qualifications true.
This is why those who argue thus not because they feel a difficulty but for the sake of argument, should say that this is not true, but true for this man. They must make everything relative-relative to opinion and perception, so that nothing either has come to be or will be without some one’s first thinking so.
But if things have come to be or will be, evidently not all things will be relative to opinion.
If a thing is one, it is in relation to one thing or to a definite number of things.
If the same thing is both half and equal, it is not to the double that the equal is correlative. If, then, in relation to that which thinks, man and that which is thought are the same, man will not be that which thinks, but only that which is thought.
If each thing is to be relative to that which thinks, that which thinks will be relative to an infinity of specifically different things.
Thus:
- the most indisputable of all beliefs is that contradictory statements are not at the same time true
- what consequences follow from the assertion that they are
- why people do assert this.
Now since it is impossible that contradictories should be at the same time true of the same thing, obviously contraries also cannot belong at the same time to the same thing. For of contraries, one is a privation no less than it is a contrary-and a privation of the essential nature; and privation is the denial of a predicate to a determinate genus.
If, then, it is impossible to affirm and deny truly at the same time, it is also impossible that contraries should belong to a subject at the same time, unless both belong to it in particular relations, or one in a particular relation and one without qualification.